William A. Earle
The Ontological Argument in Spinoza
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 11 (1951)
The ontological argument is universally discredited today, generally
on logical grounds. It has become a platitude to assert that existence cannot
follow from essence, that all analytic propositions are to be interpreted as
hypotheses having no existential import. Our platitudes, however, would be falsehoods
resting on an inadequate metaphysical analysis for a series of thinkers including
Anselm, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Hegel, and Bradley. At each period the contemporaries
of these men raised our objections for us and these objections were not unknown
to the philosophers who rested their entire work on the ontological argument.
At each period these philosophers insisted that the objections rested on a misunderstanding
of precisely what the argument did and did not assert. Such misunderstandings
will occur as long as we abstract the ontological argument from its metaphysical
context; that is, as long as we alter the significance of the relevant terms.
Since this entire context is probably clearest in Spinoza, I should like to reexamine
the ontological argument as it occurs there in order to determine whether we
are not committing the same errors of misinterpretation as did his contemporaries.
But before a discussion of the ontological argument proper, I should
like to clarify the relation of this paper to that argument. I do not intend
to “prove” the ontological argument in a direct fashion, since such a procedure
would be in direct contradiction to the assertions of the argument. The argument
states in some fashion that the existence of God or substance follows from his
essence alone; to attempt then to give further grounds for the existence of God
than those asserted by the argument would be to destroy that argument. The argument
must stand or fall by itself; the only function of this discussion is to elucidate
the argument, and not to prove it.
Briefly the argument states that there is an essence
whose existence follows necessarily from that essence. That is all. It does not
say: I have an idea of such an essence, and therefore God must exist as cause.
Nor does it say: there are certain finite things, hence there must be a necessary
being as cause. These are both variants of the cosmological argument, and although
used by Spinoza, were considered by him to be a posteriori and of inferior
certitude. Both rest upon a certain empirical fact, the existence of a certain
sort of idea or of finite things; and both employ certain notions of causation
which we cannot analyze here. But these considerations are irrelevant to the
argument in its pure form, which asserts only that there is an essence which
necessarily involves existence.
Spinoza does not assert that all essences involve existence,
nor that essence as such involves existence. Here he would insist that most essences
do not and cannot involve existence. The question concerns only one special essence,
the essence of substance, or of that “which is in itself and conceived through
itself.” This one, Spinoza asserts, must involve existence; and to see why, we
must know what Spinoza means by the terms, “essence,” “existence,” and “substance.”
Let us first examine the notion of essence. Essence, for Spinoza,
is not a purely logical term, the mere object of any definable sign. Essence
expresses something positive, it expresses power or reality. It is certainly
not what Santayana for example means by essence, a term wide enough to include
square circles, as well as negations of these, etc. “Non-chair” for Santayana
is an essence in the same sense as chair, though for Spinoza it would be a mere
fiction of the mind, a mere word. From such a conception we could derive no positive
properties; we would know only what the thing was not. “Positive” and “negative,”
however, are slippery terms, since a word verbally negative may express something
positive, as does the word “infinite,” for example. Essences cannot be self-contradictory
and since the entire course of nature follows analytically from God who does
all that he can do, it follows that there arc only essences for those things
which were, are, or will be. Anything else must either contradict itself, or
contradict what exists. Such unrealizables will be mere fictions of the mind
or compositions of words.
Secondly, and more importantly, an essence is
not an idea, or a psychological state of some sort. Spinoza distinguishes
between the idea and the ideatum. The idea of a circle would therefore
have two aspects: it is, to be sure, an idea, a mode of thought; but it is the
idea of a circle which is not a mode of thought, but a determinate mode
of extension. The circle is round, and all its radii are equal, whereas it would
be absurd to speak of an idea as being round or having radii. Thought and extension
have distinct properties, and neither is to be understood in terms of the other.
This distinction is clear within the idea; an analysis of the idea itself
will exhibit these two aspects. An idea of a house for example is clearly in
one sense a psychological act, a mode of thought; but the idea is of something
which is made of stone, wood, and bricks, and not ideas. The essence of house
or of circle, therefore, neither is nor involves the notion of thought. It is
independent of that psychological act which thinks it, and this can be seen within
that psychological act itself. This distinguishability of idea and ideatum is
essential to the objective and independent validity of thought. A geometer resolves
the circle into its proper elements, planes, lines, and the central point; at
no point need he mention the thought which is thinking all this. No geometry
will be found to posit among its principles ideas as such or anything else psychological.
Geometry and logic are sciences independent of psychology, studying objective
relations among the things posited.
Not all ideata are essences of course. But here we are interested
in those ideata which are essences and their structural and essential
independence from the psychological act by which they are thought. That they
are independent can be guaranteed within thought itself simply by the complete
analysis of the essence thought of.
These relations hold even when we take as the object of some thought
thought itself. If I have the idea of an idea, then the thought which I am thinking
of is independent of the particular act of thought by which I think it. Now this
should not be understood as asserting that we can think of essences without thinking
at all; such would be obviously nonsense, and is asserted by nobody. But it would
be asserted that there are aspects within any idea which are logically, structurally,
and essentially independent of the act which thinks them, that such a distinction
can be demonstrated within thought itself (by the reduction of the particular
essence to its principles), and that the independence of any eidetic science
from empirical psychology depends upon this distinction.
The conclusion of all this is simply that essences are not ideas,
although sometimes ideas are ideas of essences the essences do not require that
particular act of thought for their definition, and hence are structurally independent.
This is a first step in the perception of the independence of essence: its independence
from mind; it does not yet demonstrate that there are essences which are as a
matter of fact existentially independent of everything.
Essences then are independent of the psychological act which thinks
them; but, considered in themselves, they may be dependent upon other essences,
or they may be absolutely independent. The essence of circle depends, among other
things, on the essence of plane, of line, etc., since these other essences would
figure in its definition. This order of derivation is of course logical, but
it is mirrored in the level of existing things: an existing circle depends on
an existing plane. The essence of island requires the essence of circumambient
water; and so an existing island requires existing circumambient water. The order
of essences and things is one and the same. A thing is a mode when it is conceived
through another, and the essence of that mode will depend on the essence of that
through which it is conceived. And just as the independence of essence from thought
is discoverable within thought itself simply by the analysis of the essence,
so the dependence or independence of the essence from other essences will be
discoverable within thought alone by the adequate analysis of that essence. An
independent essence will be one which is conceived through itself and
which is in itself. These phrases clearly express the same thing: since
things will depend existentially upon precisely those things on which
their essences will essentially depend, independence of essence is the
same as independence of existence. The discernment, therefore, of an essence
which is thought through itself will be at the same time the discernment of that
which exists through itself; defining the essence is precisely this act of discernment;
hence as soon as God or substance is defined as being precisely that essence
which is thought through itself, i.e., which is essentially independent, it is
seen at the same time that he must exist.
But what kind of existence does such an essence have? Here again
we must not import into Spinoza’s system conceptions of existence fundamentally
foreign to it. For Spinoza there are two sorts of existence: eternity, and duration.
Duration is that existence which modes have, and is measured by time; eternity
is the existence which independent essences have. When Spinoza speaks of the
existence of God he is not attributing to God some sort of surd, some irrational,
brute, simply given mode of being; the existence of God, he tells us, is nothing
but his essence: they are one and the same thing. To assert God’s existence,
therefore, is to frame an analytic proposition. One is not adding an extrinsic
property to an essence; ultimately the argument is simply the reaffirmation of
the absolute independence of God’s essence. It is analytic, and therefore requires
no additional grounds.
To attribute to God an existence which would add a new determinant
to his essence would be to attribute to him the existence appropriate to modes,
duration. We cannot know by an analysis of the essence of modes whether they
exist or not; we must consult the order of nature which is to say, for finite
minds, we must consult experience. Hence to interpret the ontological argument
as attempting to prove a synthetic proposition by something like “rational intuition”
is to misinterpret it completely. The argument was never anything but an analytic
assertion. Whether such a proposition, along with the metaphysics derived from
it is held to be “interesting,” “fruitful,” or “useful” or not depends on what
sort of knowledge one is seeking; the ultimate use of such knowledge or any knowledge
is a question which more properly falls within ethics, and is a question not
neglected of course by Spinoza.
The existence of God is therefore his eternity, and his eternity
is again the radical independence of his essence. He is substance, and substance
is that which is and is conceived through itself. So again we see, now by an
explication of the term, “existence,” that the argument is analytic. But why,
it may be asked, do we not end with nothing rather than infinite substance consisting
of infinite attributes, each one of which expresses infinite essence? This would
be an objection only so long as we forgot Spinoza’s conception of essence; it
is positive rather than negative, and expresses, therefore, some positive reality,
rather than the mere negation of something which would as a matter of fact be
nothing but a fiction, and a fiction which more clearly than anything else depended
on something else, namely everything else. In a metaphor, substance at
this level is like a light shining in a dark space; since the essence in question
has already subsumed everything else under it as a modification, there is nothing
left which can contradict or oppose it; it is free to expand out infinitely.
And as darkness cannot quench light, neither can non-being destroy the being
of substance.
The existence of God is thus an eternal subsistence. The
existence or duration of modes on the other hand will differ from the eternity
of God to the degree that their essence differs from his essence. Since modes
are derived essentially, their existence will also be derived, that is to say,
they will be dependent upon the rest of the universe; existence does not follow
immediately from these essences but only from the existence of their causes,
which are, in turn, dependent upon their own causes, etc.; existence for
modes will therefore be transitory. Since the existence of a mode cannot follow
from its essence, propositions asserting its existence will be synthetic, and
experience will be needed by any finite mind in order to ascertain its truth.
We can therefore see why existence will be a brute fact, a surd, when it is asserted
of modes by finite minds; such properties will be consequences of Spinoza’s general
conception of the relation between substance and modes. But if we were to begin
with existence conceived after the fashion of duration, then clearly we could
never arrive at the notion of eternal subsistence. The ontological argument asserting
eternal subsistence would then be interpreted after the model of modes, and would
always be absurd, a “synthetic” proposition, and wholly undemonstrable. On the
other hand, beginning with the notion of an eternal subsistence, one can, if
Spinoza is correct, derive a notion of existence or duration which is appropriate
to our experiences of finite things.
In terms of this conception of the ontological argument, let us
further consider some objections which have been made. The contention has been
made, for example, that since the existence of God follows from his essence or
definition, anything could be defined into existence, by simply including “existence”
in the definition. Thus we might define a hippogriff as a “combined griffin and
horse which exists.” Would not it then analytically follow that such a creature
must exist? The reason that such a being could not exist for Spinoza is not
that the combination of horse and griffin violates some supposed rule of nature;
such we could not know by reason alone. Rather it is because the combination
of these two terms combined with the notion of existence itself contains a contradiction.
The first part of the definition, horse and griffin, determines a mode which
intrinsically depends on other things, ultimately on the whole circumambient
universe; to now assert that such a mode existed in itself would make it independent
of that universe. Similarly with the example of the “most perfect island, one
of whose perfections is existence.” An island is a piece of land surrounded by
water. Its essence requires the essence of water, and its existence depends on
the existence of the water. To then add that such an island existed in itself
would be to contradict what we posited in the first part of the definition. (And
if the island had only dependent existence, the point is granted: the
island would only exist contingently.) Clearly the same argument would apply
to any mode defined into existence. Existence follows only from certain essences,
those namely which express infinity, independence, and substance.
Kant, in the portion of the Critique devoted to the refutation
of the ontological argument, has no trouble disposing of it under the interpretation
that it presents a synthetic judgment. But, if it is analytic, he says, then
either the conception in your mind is identical with the thing, or else you have
given us nothing but a “wretched tautology.” Clearly, the argument is
analytic; that it thereby implies that the thing, God, is identical with your
conception has already been disposed of; and that it is a tautology is true,
but whether it is “wretched” or not will depend on what value we wish to place
on the analytic clarification of existence.